Considerations in the Philosophy of Ethics "beta" rough draft Part I: Goodness as the Standard When something is said to be "good", and thus to have goodness, we mean to say simply that the thing in question conforms to some standard. By this we see that, since ethics deals with the realm of the ought, and a standard is an idea of a thing, ethics would then be a subset of standards, namely those standards by which things are correctly and rightly, judged. For instance, when we say that a piece of pie is good, we hold the pie to the standard of pleasantness, or tastiness, finding that the pie indeed fits this standard, and thus call it good. Further, when we choose this standard by which to judge a thing, we also say that the standard in question is the correct one. Perhaps correct for this situation, for this person, etc., but essentially that the standard is correct in its use. For the pie again, we may say that the pie is good or bad dependent upon how it holds up to the standard of tastiness, but when another eats the pie and finds it wanting for the standard, they may say that the pie is not good or bad. It seems then that the first distinction which needs to be drawn in the elucidation of some standard of goodness is to what it applies. Clearly we cannot reasonably say that the pie is BOTH good and bad, and yet disagreements among tasters may claim it so. The solution in this case is to clarify by saying that the _eating_ of the pie by person X is good, while the _eating_ of the pie by person Y is bad (for example) because of the differing tastes of the eaters. This would solve the delima by no longer claiming that the pie in itself is good or bad, but pushing the application of the standard back to the taster. By thus we see that clarifying how some standard rightly applies can solve seeming paradoxes in goodness and badness. As another case of clarifying a standard, we may find those who judge things by their fitness to the arbitrary whims of man. Should someone at one time find the pie good because of it's taste, and later bad because of the weight it puts on the eater, and then later good because of the pleasure it brings as an applicant to a clowns face, we would seem to have brought on another delima where the use or eating of the pie by some person is both good and bad. In this case, though, we find that the standard is actually a more complex one, where the pie is good when eaten, but only if the eating would not add weight, and only when the opportunity to apply the pie to a clowns face is not present. A standard fitting the whims of man, often called "usefulness", might cover such a case, but may simply be complex, as was stated. A standard, however, is always present in the judging of the goodness of some thing, and the falling short of such a standard is then called bad. The standard, however, is also considered the correct one, since one does not hold something to a faulty standard without knowing it as such, and would call such an irrelevent standard. Incorrect standards, while still standards, would be those not included in the considerations of ethics or a subject for debate in ethics. It is the inquiry into the correctness of the standards used which is the subject of the philosophy of ethics, and the standard of human conduct which is the more particular subject of ethics. Part II: Being In understanding the ethical standard as being a standard by which a thing is judged, we must admit the distinction between a standard as a notion of how a thing ought to be, and between things as they are. Often referred to as the distinction between the IS and the OUGHT, we find that this difference is indeed true, and indeed needs to be if ethics and standards are to be understood at all. To make this clear, let us consider the broken car. To some end, we tend to call a car good when it runs correctly, and operates as it ought to. Yet, as many of us are only too aware, a car does not always operate so simply because it ought to. Bad engines and leaking radiators provide a clear case of the distinction between standards and existence. Indeed, were there no such distinction at all, we would fail to judge things at all, since things would necessarily be as they ought to, and all things could be said good or bad without the need to judge them. Wouldn't the standard itself be, exist, in the mind of the thinker, however? Certainly, the idea of the standard is necessary to judging the goodness or badness of things, yet we realize that a thing goes on being good or bad (according to the standard) irregardless of whether we, or anyone, is considering it at present. Indeed, even if the standard by which we judge things is incorrect, we know that something would go on being good or bad by the correct standard, and would not depend on our knowledge of it as such. And so, just as the standard is distinct of existence, so the idea of the standard does not conflict with this insight. Confusion occurs from time to time concerning judging according to a standard and things as they are. Indeed, we call the very perception of things as they are to be judging, after a sense, as when we say that we judge this to be a car, and that to be a man. In this, however, we are holding our perception of a thing up to our notion of the thing we call it. In judging a car to be a car, we hold the collection of perceptions we receive with the standard of carness, judge the two to match, and call the perceived thing a car accordingly. Since our standard here is of what a car is, and not how it ought to be, we cannot be said to be considering ethics in this sense of "judging". "Judging" in the sense it is meant in ethics is similar though, as some notion of how a thing ought to be is held in to the way it is, if the two match, then the thing is judged good, and otherwise it is judged bad, having some deficiency. The consequences of this realization of the distinction of existence and ethics are significant. Consider the very common question in ethics: "Ought this be?" and "Ought we make this or that to be?". In this case, the standard being judged is one of the existence of the thing itself-- a thing's very being is the standard being questioned. This, in itself, should not be considered examples of is-ought confusion firstly, since indeed a standard _outside_ of existence is still being used to judge the existence of some thing. Secondly, it seems certain that however we might affect the forms of things, we human beings are not ourselves responsible for the existence of things, the laws of nature we take advantage of, or of the cosmos in general. With these in mind, it is likewise certain that these particular questions of ethics mentioned above cannot themselves be counted among considerations of human ethics, although they very often are. While these are indeed important considerations in the philosophy of ethics, they do not concern human ethics, and are thus put aside for the present. With all of this in mind now, we move to the next topic, that of human blame. Part III: Blame Blame is the problem of judging what is the ultimate, efficient, or agent cause of some act which is good or bad. Consider a shard of glass from a broken window on a table. The glass itself, not being the cause of its own location, would not then be blamed for being where it is. Its location is the result of the breaking of the window, caused in turn by the striking of the window by the baseball, caused in turn by the swinging of the bat, caused in turn by the movement of the arm, by the signal from a boy's brain. Of course, the laws of physics and nature also come into play, but we will place these questions aside for the moment. And so, is this signal from the boy's brain an agent cause? Ought we then blame the boy? Since human ethics deals with the standards by which we judge human action, and since these judgements require that the humans judged are able to be blamed for these actions (are the efficient cause of these decisions to act), we must conclude then that proper human ethics requires that human beings be initiators, or uncaused (free) agents-- the efficient cause of their decisions. Much debate has dealt with the question of the human free will, and it seems concluded by modernity that man is without such an aspect, and does not differ from the animals in this respect. How human ethics can be considered at all without this benefit of blame is difficult to see, however. Consider the fatalist view. Mankind, like the broken window, is but an intermediary in an endless series of causes. To blame one link in this series of inefficient causes would then be an incorrect understanding of blame. The question still remains then, is blame required for ethics? Consider the notion of deciding goodness and badness of action without the free will. In the first place, we would lose our objective judgement, as the very act of judging (in itself a free act otherwise, with the will to think and consider one aspect of a question or another entirely in the thinker) would have its cause in nature, whose good will and accuracy we would be impotent to consider. In the second place, and quite simply, morality is understood as those acts which ought to be chosen, but choosing can not in turn be understood without a chooser as an agent cause. And so, in either case, it seems that human ethics requires a free will to be present. Our present topic aside, the dispute over the existence of a free will in man, shown to be a requirement for our moral considerations, is still denied or doubted by some. Of these, some attempt to explain a basis for morality without a human will, and do so in vain. Of others who hold this view, they derive from their assumption, and rightly derive, that this assumption is destructive of ethics, and they assert moral relativism. Consider now the boy as an agent cause of his own actions. Moving the body to act, he becomes the cause of the shard of glass upon the table. He is not the efficient cause, however, which means that he may not be entirely blamed for the glass. The glass itself is an effect of its creator, and the ball's flight an effect of the laws of nature and physics. How then do these bare in ethical questions? Here it is difficult. Some say that these effects ultimately go to God, and that since He is good, his acts are also so (such as the creating of the laws of nature, and the sand of the glass, etc.) Others say nature is eternal or cyclical, and the laws of nature without an agent cause, and thus there is none to blame for them. In either case, the deciding case for the ultimate cause of the glass' location, where a moral question is concerned, remains in the boy. He is blamable, unlike a cyclical nature, and he may act good or bad, and thus is unlike the acts of God. Now, do not confuse our topic as pertaining to the goodness or badness of the location of the glass. As mentioned previously, the shared blame is only partially the boy's, and the others become irrelevent as stated. This concludes this discussion of the nature of ethics. Now some particular opinions and observations about virtue, or correct action by an agent, and the relationship of ethics to the philosophy of man are considered. Part IV: Passions Irregardless of whether one acknowledges the free agency of man necessary to the consideration of him morally, all recognize the animal aspect of man, and how it is subject to certain passions. A passion is understood here as the subjection of the body to certain things in nature. The light to our eyes, the sound to our ears, and the ground to our feet are all causes of our passions. But less obvious things, such as chemicals and drugs of various sorts, also subject the body to their dispositions, and we feel them. Of the passions, it seems there are two sorts. One is a violent passion, such as being forcibly held down, or being drugged. These are known by their taking away from the man some ability to act, though they do not always affect the will to act. The other would then be the nonviolent, such as sight or sound, which neither takes away an ability to act, or the will to act. Some might argue, however, that all passions affect ability in some way, and that even the seemingly passive passions, such as sight and sound, affect the ability to hear and see other things also. This might be granted, so long as it is acknowledged that the will to act is unaffected by neither sort. It might also be said that certain passions affect the will, and that those which bring death are among them. This might also be granted, though it is a bit beyond the scope of this discussion at this time. With this understanding in mind now, we find that the passions affect discussions of ethics in a couple of ways. One of these ways is in arguments concerning what an ethic is. Typically it will be said that because of some passion, say that of sexual urges for instance, one ought take steps to alleviate their circumstances. In this case, as others, it is typically granted that since one's urge is to do something, they therefore _will_ do something, and (by implication) it is correct to do so. Clearly, however, when a statement of being, such as "man has such and such an urge" is used to defend an assertion "man therefore ought to do such and such", a fallacy of confusing the is with the ought is being committed, as was discussed before. This argument also points to a more subtle assumption also, hinted at above, that because some passion exists, that the passion will therefore be followed. However, this assumption is antithetical to the assertion defended above that man's will is free, without which blame and ethics can not be considered. Another way in which the passions enter discussions of ethics concerns more closely the ability of violent passions to prevent moral actions from being done. Here an important point about the relationship of the will to morality needs to be made. It is true that some passion or another may prevent someone from acting as they ought, but this brings up the all important point mentioned previously, that man can not be held responsible for the acts of nature around him, or the circumstances of both nature and body which may prevent him from acting. Like the ball breaking the glass, even if the existence of the ball and its flight could be wholey placed in the thrower, surely the placement of the window can not, and the boy can not for this be blamed. Likewise the very laws of nature which governed the balls flight are not the fault of the boys. For what then _can_ he be blamed. It seems indeed that one aspect of man's nature is above the simple passions, both violent and passive, and beyond the laws of nature and the existence of things wholey out of his control. This is the human will, and it is from this morality springs. We call the simple efficient chosing of the will an intention, and it is intent indeed from which blame springs. We can not blame the boy that nature did not cooperate with his intentions, but we can blame him for those intentions more assuredly, as these intentions have their sole efficient source in his agency. We can likewise blame him for not intending to consider his actions before willing them, and for not choosing to be careful. Part V: Authority Here we consider how one comes to know of moral things, and from where moral edicts spring. In the first place, we must recall the state in which any moral edict exists may not be as an essence of some existent thing. Were this so, we would be back to the state mentioned previously, in which goodness and badness is part of the nature of things, fails to be a standard by which things may be judged, and thus things are no longer truely capable of being good or ill. Now, this is fine for things not morally considered, such as the standard for existent things in themselves, for which we may not be blamed. However, such a position for the acts of men is anachronistic to ethics. With an ethical edict then as a standard, devoid of existence, we find that the form a standard can at best take on is as an idea, from which a judgement may be made about goodness and badness. This requires then that a mind be present to receive the standard. Without a mind in which ethics is contained for the purpose of judging, it cannot then be said that there is an ethics at all. Why is this? For the reason stated before-- an ethic is a standard devoid of necessary being, either as some mystical Platonic "form", or as actual existence. We call these notions then, which may or may not be existing, but which are comprehended and considered, "ideas", of which a standard is certainly a subset. Now we must consider how these edicts indeed become necessary, and from where they spring. Clearly, since a standard exists firstly and by nature as an idea, and states how a thing (and more particularly an act) is to be judged good or bad, we find that it must indeed be a particular conscious thing which first holds this idea. This is the mind holding the ethic, previously mentioned. When considering the nature of the mind holding such an idea, certainly an omniscient mind is sufficient for the purpose, but not necessary. If a particular standard is indeed a true standard, and one by which actions and things are judged, then the mind holding it would, by definition, be an authority on the ethics of the thing in question. An omniscient mind, in turn, would be an authority on goodness in general, as it would hold all standards. However, this does not assist in the determination of what a true ethic is. After all, many claim to be authorities on these very subjects, though their assertions contradict. This is to say that there is nothing in the nature of consciousness which requires that it know moral answers, though the existence of moral answers requires that there be a mind to know them. But then we find that an omniscient mind is the only necessary authority, while all lesser minds are only incidental authorities on moral questions. Now, since nothing necessary (such as a true moral standard of good) may come from an incidental source, we find that moral answers require a necessary source. Now, as to the source of moral edicts, let us again consider what their source may be from their nature. In the first place, from what we know above about false authorities; we know we require an authoritative mind to know a moral standard. Again, a standard may not be an existant form to maintain it's meaning as a standard, but can only be an ideal of some perfection in a mind, whose authority we can derive from the true knowledge of moral answers it contains. Secondly, to be a source of moral edicts, the authoritative mind must be prior to the matters to which the standards pertain. This can be seen since while the things to which morality and standards apply to are contingent things (some act can not be considered good or bad if it is never done, and a dog can never be a good thing if its parents never mate), while moral standards are necessary, these standards then must be with regard for their incidental subjects. It is from the matters discussed above we find our most important insight thusfar-- for there to be morality, there must be a necessary, authoritative mind which exists, and this mind must be prior to all things which may be judged. Part VI: Nature Underlying some thought is a notion of the goodness or badness of bringing things to be, and how human ethics is to be judged thus. It is usually said then that since the existence of some thing or event is good or bad, then the acts of men preceding these things and events in nature must also be good or bad. An example would be that of poverty, which many universally believe ought not exist. It is then said that that which precedes, causes, etc the elimination of poverty must therefore be a good act. This is then brought back to the discussion above by noting that in every case some condition of man is considered to be a bad or good condition, and that good or bad acts can be therefore derived. The error here begins with an understanding of incidental effects. Certainly when one wills to move his arm, the arm moves. However, when one wills to fly, one does not necessarily rise. We find then that the effects following an act of willing are indeed incidental to the act of willing in itself. Since ethics deals with good and bad acts of willing, it would seem to cover these acts only, without regard to the fact that they may or may not have incidental effects. Even on fairly clear cases, such as one man killing another with a gun deriving that it was a bad act to will to pull the trigger (which would seem to cover a true ethical matter), we find that were the man limp in his hand, his willing to pull the trigger would suddenly not be a bad act (since it results in no death), which is an absurdity with the above statement that willing to pull the trigger IS bad. Saving our obhorance of murder, it should be noted that it is willing to murder which is the bad act, not the willing to pull the trigger. Hypocracy. Naturalism & the mean. Part VII: Modernity Part VIII: God Part IX: Political Theory Part X: Ignorance